- Details
-
Written by Norman G. Finkelstein Norman G. Finkelstein
-
Category: News News
-
Published: 26 November 2007 26 November 2007
-
Last Updated: 26 November 2007 26 November 2007
-
Created: 26 November 2007 26 November 2007
-
Hits: 6594 6594
The Camp David II Negotiations: How Dennis Ross Proved the Palestinians Aborted the Peace Process
Issue 142 (Winter 2007) |
Journal of Palestine Studies |
Abstract
by Norman G. Finkelstein
Dennis Ross's
The Missing Peace: The Inside Story of the Fight for Middle East Peace[1]
has been widely heralded as the definitive treatment of the
Israeli-Palestinian "peace process" from the 1993 Oslo Accords through
the Camp David negotiations of July 2000.
[2]
The "one overriding lesson from the story of the peace process," Ross
writes in his prologue, "is that truth-telling is a necessity" (p. 14).
The "purpose" of his book as well as the "key to peace," he similarly
concludes, "is to debunk mythologies . . . to engage in truth-telling"
(p. 773). Ross's execution of this debunking and truth-telling
enterprise, however, is problematic. His account of the peace process
is based almost entirely on his memory and notes. Its authority derives
chiefly from the fact that he was the "point person" (p. 106) for the
Clinton administration on the Arab-Israeli conflict. Yet his "inside
story" of the Camp David negotiations differs fundamentally on crucial
points from what other participants have said and written. Rather than
go over the ground already covered,
[3]
I will focus here on the cluster of assumptions informing Ross's
account of what happened during the negotiations and why, and the
distortions that spring from these assumptions.
Ross's
interpretation of why Camp David failed gained wide currency almost
immediately. His narrative, as is well known, assigns the lion's share
of blame for the summit's collapse to Palestinian leader Yasir Arafat.
Nonetheless, Ross situates the failure in a deeper Palestinian
pathology.
The Root of the Problem It is a central contention of
Ross that Palestinians are in thrall to a victim syndrome. While
acknowledging that they "surely have suffered" (p. 775), Ross maintains
that the Palestinians' "sense of being victims has . . . fostered a
sense of entitlement" (p. 42; cf. pp. 200, 686). For instance,
Palestinians harbor the belief that they had been "entitled to the
land" on which they were born when Zionist settlers coming from Europe
sought to displace them; that the land "was theirs and had been taken"
(p. 35). In Palestinian "eyes," Ross continues, "they were not
responsible for what was done to the Jews in Europe" (p. 42). In their
"eyes," consequently, "ending the conflict and agreeing to live with
Israel's presence" constituted a significant concession (p. 44).
Further, Palestinians chafed at the fact that it was Israel that
determined the pace and parameters of withdrawal from the occupied
Palestinian territory because they "believed they were getting what was
rightfully theirs" (p. 55) and that "the land is 'theirs'" (p. 763).
Their opposition to Israeli settlement expansion apparently sprang from
this misapprehension as well: "it outrage[d] the Palestinians—absorbing
land that they considered to be theirs" (pp. 82, 195), "perceived to be
theirs" (p. 765), that "they believed was theirs or should be theirs"
(p. 332; cf. 44, 55). Finally, Arafat "flew into a rage" and "ranted
for several minutes" after seeing the Oslo map because of the
"appearance" that the Palestinian areas comprised "isolated islands
that are cut off from each other" (p. 205). It so happens, however,
that what Palestinians "believed," "considered," and "perceived" to be
theirs actually
was
theirs according to international law; that it was not just "in their
eyes," but in those of any rational person that, whatever sins
Palestinians might be chastised for, causing the Nazi holocaust is not
one of them; and that the Oslo map did in fact shatter the Palestinian
territory into a maze of fragments.
Compounding Palestinian misapprehensions regarding their legitimate
claims on Palestine, according to Ross, were those regarding the United
Nations and international law. For example, Ross writes:
Palestinians and many in the Arab world
continued to see an American double standard. . . . They asked why was
Israel permitted to effectively ignore Security Council resolutions
while Saddam was forced to comply? They did not see the difference
between the Security Council resolutions. Those against Iraq came as a
response to Saddam's eradication of a member state of the U.N.; the
resolutions required his compliance, not his acceptance. Noncompliance
carried sanctions, and led to the use of force against his absorption
of Kuwait. The resolutions that Palestinians and Arabs more generally
focused on with regard to Israel were resolutions 242 and 338. They
were adopted after the 1967 and 1973 wars. They provided the guidelines
or principles that should shape negotiations to resolve the conflict
between Arabs and Israelis. The terms of a final peace settlement were
not established in these resolutions and they could not be mandatory on
either side. But drawing distinctions between Security Council
resolutions involving the Iraqis and the Israelis was not satisfying.
The Arab world generally rejected the idea that Iraq faced pressure to
implement Security Council resolutions while Israel did not. They
wanted equal treatment. They wanted to portray all Security Council
resolutions as having the force of international law. For the Arab
world generally, the resolutions were their face-savers. They would
resolve the conflict with Israel, but only on the basis of
international law, "international legitimacy," as they called it. Here
was their explanation, their justification for ending the conflict. If
Iraq had to follow international legitimacy, so too, must Israel. (p.
43)
This argument poses some problems, however. Security Council
resolutions regarding Iraq, we are told, focused on its violations of
international law, thereby requiring "compliance" and carrying
"sanctions," whereas Security Council resolutions regarding Israel
focused on "principles" for a settlement, thereby requiring
"acceptance" and envisaging "negotiations." Yet the international
community over the last thirty years has reached broad consensus on the
principles for settlement of the Israel-Palestine conflict. They are
embodied in UN resolution 242 and subsequent UN resolutions calling for
full Israeli withdrawal from the West Bank and Gaza and the
establishment of a Palestinian state in these areas in exchange for
recognition of Israel's right to live in peace and security with its
neighbors.
[4]
Each year the overwhelming majority of UN member states votes in favor
of this two-state settlement, while each year Israel and the United
States (along with this or that South Pacific atoll) oppose it. It is
unclear why principles that find overwhelming support in the UN require
compliance and carry sanctions in the case of Iraq's refusal to
withdraw from occupied Kuwait but not in the case of Israel's refusal
to withdraw from the occupied Palestinian territory. In fact, Israel's
refusal to abide by this longstanding international consensus
apparently puts its occupation squarely in the same category as Iraq's
illegal occupation of Kuwait. "[A]n occupation regime that refuses to
earnestly contribute to efforts to reach a peaceful solution should be
considered illegal," Tel Aviv University law professor Eyal Benvenisti
opines:
Indeed, such a refusal should be
considered outright annexation. The occupant has a duty under
international law to conduct negotiations in good faith for a peaceful
solution. It would seem that an occupant who proposes unreasonable
conditions, or otherwise obstructs negotiations for peace for the
purpose of retaining control over the occupied territory, could be
considered a violator of international law.[5]
"The continued rule of the recalcitrant occupant," Benvenisti adds, should be construed "as an aggression."
[6]
In addition, Arabs and Palestinians have focused not, as Ross alleges,
on UN resolutions 242 and 338 when calling for Israel's compliance and
sanctions against it, but rather on Israel's violation of scores of
Security Council and General Assembly resolutions deploring its illegal
annexation of Jerusalem (and the Syrian Golan Heights), its illegal
settlement activity in the West Bank and Gaza, its illegal invasion and
occupation of Lebanon (and other Arab countries), and numerous other
flagrant violations of international law.
[7]
If the Arab world has not drawn "distinctions" between these
resolutions and those directed at Iraq, it is perhaps because there are
none to be drawn. It merits notice that Israel falls into a category
all its own regarding compliance and sanctions. Although the Security
Council has imposed sanctions on member states on some twenty different
occasions since 1990, often for violations of international law
identical to those committed by Israel, the U.S. veto has shielded
Israel from any such sanctions.
[8]
Again, if the Arab world "continued to see an American double
standard," it is perhaps because there in fact has been one, and if the
Arab world demanded "equal treatment" for Palestinians "on the basis of
international law," it is not self-evident why this should be
objectionable.
Ross as Witness
Before scrutinizing Ross's influential thesis on why Camp David failed,
it bears pausing for a moment on his reliability as a witness to these
negotiations. Although acknowledging that he was publicly the
whipping-boy for the Palestinians, Ross is emphatic that in reality
they "respected me" (p. 608). He reports telling Palestinian
negotiators, "You know that I understand your problems, your needs, and
your aspirations very well. You know that I often explain them better
than any of you do" (p. 755). Yet, the evidence suggests that, whether
deservedly or not, Ross's Arab interlocutors "couldn't stand" him and
believed he was "in league with the Israelis."
[9]
Moreover, where Ross's allegedly verbatim account of the actual
negotiations can be crosschecked, it proves misleading. Consider the
volatile exchange between U.S. President Bill Clinton and the
Palestinian delegation on day five of the summit. The Palestinians
apparently insisted that before bargaining over land swaps, Israel had
to accept the June 1967 borders as a baseline: whatever land
Palestinians conceded on these borders would have to be compensated.
Clinton, however, demanded that Palestinians exchange maps with Israel
without Israel committing itself to the June borders as the baseline.
Here is Ross's rendering of what ensued:
The President had had enough, and he let
it rip. He said this was an outrageous approach. He had risked a great
deal in having this summit. He had been advised not to take this risk.
He disregarded this advice because he felt it necessary to do all he
could to reach an agreement. But this was an outrageous waste of his
time and everyone else's time. He had offered a reasonable approach
that did not compromise Palestinian interests. They lost nothing by
trying it, and Abu Ala was simply not willing to negotiate. No one
could accept what he was asking for. He [Clinton] would not be a part
of something not serious, and this wasn't serious, it was a mockery.
Arafat had given his agreement to what the President was asking for and
now he comes to the meetings and finds an outrageous approach—and he
repeated, shouting now, "an outrageous approach." At this point, the
President stood up and stalked out. (p. 668)
Yet, judging by authoritative accounts, Ross omitted a crucial passage
from Clinton's reproach to the Palestinian negotiators: "This isn't the
Security Council here. This isn't the UN General Assembly. . . . I'm
the president of the United States."
[10]
Thus, even while rejecting the Palestinian position, Clinton implicitly
acknowledged—correctly—that the Palestinians were merely reiterating UN
resolutions and international law calling for full Israeli withdrawal
from the occupied Palestinian territory, with allowance for minor and
mutual land swaps.
Barak Gives, Arafat Pockets The essence of Ross's
explanation for Camp David's failure, repeatedly set forth, is that
whereas Barak made huge concessions at Camp David, Arafat, having a
"tendency to pocket" (p. 686), made none: "we kept moving toward
[Arafat] without much movement from him" (p. 686); "the summit was
about to collapse. The President had made his best effort, and now so
had Barak. Arafat had said no to everything" (p. 693); "I had had it
with [Arafat]. . . . here at Camp David he had not presented a single
idea or single serious comment in two weeks" (p. 705); "he could not
compromise or concede in order to end the conflict" (p. 767);
"Palestinians . . . must give up the illusion that Arafat fostered:
that they did not have to compromise on land or on refugees or on
Jerusalem, and maybe most important, that they did not have to be
responsible" (p. 775); "the Arafat legacy [is] rejecting compromise on
the permanent status issues of Jerusalem, refugees and borders" (p.
808; cf. 749–50).
To assess Ross's thesis, it is useful first to look at the framework of
what he calls the "basic trade-offs" required for resolving the
conflict:
on the western border, the Palestinians
get the 1967 lines, but with modifications to take account of the
Israeli settlements; on the eastern border, it's sovereignty for the
Palestinians, with Israel's security needs met; on refugees, it's the
general principle for the Palestinians in terms of reference to UN
General Assembly resolution 194 (not the "right of return") and its
practical limitation for the Israelis. (p. 663)
Seen in the light of international law, it is to be noticed that the
"trade-offs" Ross ticks off require fundamental concessions from
Palestinians, but none at all from Israel:
- The Palestinians must relinquish title to parts of the territory
Israel conquered in 1967, although the world's highest legal body, the
International Court of Justice, has ruled that "all these territories
(including East Jerusalem) remain occupied territories," to which
Israel has no legal title.[11]
- The Palestinians must accept the permanence of Jewish settlements,
although, again according to the International Court of Justice,
"Israeli settlements in the Occupied Palestinian Territory (including
East Jerusalem) have been established in breach of international law."[12]
- The Palestinians must concede restrictions on the right of refugees
to return to their homes, although respected human rights organizations
"call for Palestinians who fled or were expelled from Israel, the West
Bank or Gaza Strip, along with those of their descendants who have
maintained genuine links with the area, to be able to exercise their
right of return."[13]
What Ross depicts as the framework of necessary "trade-offs" and
"compromises" for peace, then, consists entirely of losses for
Palestinians and gains for Israel. Beyond this, Ross himself is obliged
to acknowledge that Palestinians
did
make "meaningful concessions" on "three settlement blocs in the West
Bank, accepting that the Jewish neighborhoods of East Jerusalem would
be Israeli, and agreeing to Israeli early-warning sites in the West
Bank" (p. 768; cf. pp. 635, 640, 667, 673-75, 723, 724-25). He also
reports that Palestinians accepted the principle of swapping Israeli
territory for the Palestinian territory Israel wanted to annex, as well
as a cap on the number of Palestinian refugees permitted to return to
Israel.
[14]
Notwithstanding such concessions, in Ross's view the Israelis proved
much more forthcoming. In his representation of the talks on day six of
the Camp David summit, for example, he typically reports that Israel
"had made big moves" (p. 674) granting Palestinian sovereignty over
three outlying Arab neighborhoods in Jerusalem and 90 percent of the
West Bank. The Palestinian negotiators stubbornly clung, however, to
the demand for equal land swaps: "once the principle of swaps was
accepted, then they could work out the modifications on the border" (p.
674), and "we recognize the Israelis have needs and we can address them
once the principle of swaps is accepted" (p. 674). He concludes his
narrative of the session as follows:
Shlomo [Ben-Ami], in summing up, had
said that he and Gilad [Sher] had come in the spirit that the President
had asked. They came to make a deal, stretching well beyond their
instructions. Unfortunately, he said, their Palestinian friends had not
come in such a spirit, but he hoped they would consider carefully
everything he had suggested and respond in kind. Saeb [Erekat]
responded, appreciating the seriousness of the discussion but also
claiming that he had gone very far on Jerusalem. He was out on a limb,
accepting Jewish neighborhoods in East Jerusalem that most Palestinians
considered illegal. Now the two sides should continue their
negotiations. Gilad got angry and said this is rock bottom for us. "You
think you can just take this as a new floor and negotiate from there.
We came to make a deal, not to go into the souk [market]" . . . In our
meeting with the President afterward, I said this is going to confirm
Barak's worst fears: he moves in a big way, Arafat pockets it, and he
is expected to move again in a way that will definitely go beyond his
redlines. . . .We cannot ask Barak for anything more; the Palestinians
have made that impossible. . . . You have to push [Arafat] back hard
and say they moved and you didn't. Enough is enough. You have to say I
cannot get you anything unless you move seriously. (pp. 674–75)
Like the Israelis, Ross testily observes, "We too had had enough of the Palestinian unwillingness to negotiate" (p. 677).
[15]
Even if one accepts for argument's sake Ross's depiction of the Israeli
position, what he deems Israel's "big moves" fell well short of what
Palestinians could rightfully claim under international law. Would Ross
have reckoned it "big moves" if the PLO had recognized Israeli
sovereignty over Tel Aviv's suburbs and 90 percent of its territory
within the pre-June 1967 borders? Ross acknowledges that the
Palestinians had offered concessions on Jerusalem and on Israeli
settlements based on the June 1967 borders and the principle of land
swaps. In other words, what Ross deems the Palestinian "unwillingness
to negotiate" met, and even surpassed, their legal obligations, while
what "Arafat pockets" is what Palestinians were legally entitled to.
One doesn't recall Ross reckoning it a "tendency to pocket" when
Israeli leaders obtained Palestinian recognition of Israel's 1949
borders. A fitter use of the locution would perhaps be that Israel
denied Palestinians their legally sanctioned rights while
simultaneously pocketing the Palestinians' full recognition of them.
"We have recognized Israel and agreed to its demands for secure
borders, security arrangements and cooperation and coordination in
security matters," a Palestinian negotiator complained a year after
Camp David. "You pocketed this incredible historical concession and
made more demands."
[16]
Palestinian demands appear maximal while Palestinian concessions appear
minimal because Ross ignores international law. It is not just "most
Palestinians" who considered Israeli settlements in East Jerusalem
"illegal," but international law as well. Allowing Israel to retain
many of these settlements therefore constituted a huge Palestinian
concession; yet, in Ross's account it goes unnoticed because the
settlements' illegality is depicted as a Palestinian "perception."
Similarly, with regard to Palestinian refugees, Ross explains that
Israel could not recognize the principle of their right of return (let
alone its implementation) because "no Israeli prime minister could be
expected to make gut-wrenching compromises on all issues" (p. 743). For
Israel to recognize in principle the Palestinian right of return,
however, would signify not a compromise but the bare minimum
recognition of a legal obligation. The real compromise would be for
Palestinians to forfeit this right—which is exactly what they did, if
not in principle, then in its restricted implementation. Mutatis
mutandis this likewise applies to Israel's "gut-wrenching compromises"
whether at Oslo or Camp David: the Israelis might have had to settle
for much less than they
wanted, but the Palestinians had to settle for much less than they were
owed.
To curb one's desires is fundamentally different from surrendering
one's rights. In disregarding international law, Ross obscures this
crucial distinction. Concomitantly, he obscures the fact that
throughout the peace process, all the genuine concessions came from the
Palestinian side.
[17]
From Rights to "Needs" Ross does not simply ignore
international law, however; he explicitly repudiates it. No doubt aware
that the standard of rights is an encumbrance on his thesis, Ross
substitutes for it the standard of "needs." Once having appointed
himself the supreme arbiter of each side's needs, it is child's play
for Ross to demonstrate Palestinian culpability. Thus, whereas Israeli
demands mirrored their needs, Palestinian demands exceeded theirs:
ergo, Palestinians bore sole responsibility for Camp David's failure.
The case Ross mounts is irrefutable because it is tautological: Ross
decided that the Palestinians were blameworthy because he decided that
what Israel had offered was all the Palestinians needed.
The main innovation of Ross's narrative is to shift the framework of
the peace process from rights to needs. This novel framework serves as
(1) an analytic device to demonstrate Israeli flexibility and
Palestinian intransigence and (2) a normative device for justifying a
settlement that negates Palestinian rights. Consider Ross's
representation of the negotiations on day five of the Camp David summit
that climaxed in Clinton's outburst:
In response to an Israeli map that
showed three different colors—brown for the Palestinian state, orange
for the areas the Israelis would annex, and red for transitional
areas—Abu Ala was not prepared to discuss Israeli needs unless the
Israelis first accepted the principle of the territorial swap and
reduced the areas they sought to annex. The President at first tried to
reason with Abu Ala, explaining that he could see "why this map is not
acceptable to you. But you cannot say to them, not good enough, give me
something more acceptable; that's not negotiation. Why not say the
orange area is too big, let's talk about your needs and see how we can
reduce the orange area and turn it into brown? If we focus on the
security aspect and look at the Jordan Valley, we might discuss the
security issues and see if we can reduce the orange area." Shlomo
agreed with that approach—thereby signaling that he was open to
reducing the orange area, which amounted to close to 14 percent of the
total of the West Bank outside of Jerusalem. Abu Ala continued to
resist. As he did, and he repeated old arguments about the settlements
being illegal and the Palestinians needing the 1967 lines, the
President's face began to turn red. (pp. 667–68)
The Palestinians appear to be uncompromising because they will not
negotiate Israel's needs separately from their own rights.
Contrariwise, Israel appears to be reasonable because it is willing to
negotiate on the basis of reciprocal needs. Needs against needs: isn't
this a fair quid pro quo? Further, Israelis demonstrate flexibility by
signaling willingness to reduce their needs, whereas Palestinians
demonstrate inflexibility by not budging from their rights. Clinton
attempts to reason with the Palestinians that the basis of negotiations
is each party's presentation of its respective needs. The Palestinians
respond by insisting that each party's needs must be set within, and
subordinated to, the framework of rights: if Israel needs more than it
is legally entitled to, then it must compensate. But, according to
Clinton, a discourse of rights, not needs, is the wrong language. In
the face of such unreason and intransigence, he justifiably (in Ross's
judgment) explodes.
Yet, even Israel's "reduced needs" greatly exceeded its rights. Would
Ross have praised Palestinians' flexibility if they had reduced their
needs from 14 percent of Israeli territory to 10 percent? And would he
then have faulted Israelis for having "continued to resist"? Moreover,
whereas Palestinians seem uncompromising in Ross's account because they
refused to forego the framework of rights, one is hard-pressed to name
a conflict where negotiations were not anchored in rights. Was it
incumbent upon Kuwait to negotiate its occupation on the basis of Iraqi
needs? Earlier, Ross had explained that the U.S. negotiating strategy
started from Israeli needs "because the Israelis held the territories,
they were on the giving end" (p. 55). Was it on the basis of Iraqi
needs that the United States conducted negotiations while Iraq held the
territory of Kuwait?
Or consider Israel's negotiations with Egyptian president Anwar Sadat
on the Israeli-occupied Sinai. Prior to the 1977 Camp David summit,
Israel had emphatically insisted that Sharm al-Shaykh was "vital" to
its security, with Moshe Dayan famously declaring that he would prefer
"Sharm al-Shaykh without peace to peace without Sharm al-Shaykh."
Similarly, when the Israeli-Egyptian negotiations at Camp David
commenced, Israel asserted that the oil refineries, airfields, and
settlements it had built in the Sinai constituted irreducible needs—and
it bargained hard to retain them. Yet ultimately, it had to abandon all
these "needs" on account of Egypt's legal title to the territory.
[18]
Ross's entire narrative of Camp David is firmly embedded in this
framework of needs. He reports that on the eve of the summit Israel had
formulated "a basis for success": if Palestinians acquiesced in
"modifying the Green Line to take account of . . . Israel's needs,"
while Israel made the "concession" of giving Palestinians the eastern
border along the Jordan River, it "would mark the end of the conflict"
(p. 636). He reports that on day one of the summit the United States
proposed that the Green Line "would be modified as necessary" to meet
Israeli "settlement bloc requirements." Although Palestinians had made
clear that they "needed" the June 1967 border or a land swap as
compensation, the United States decided "not to introduce the concept
of a swap at this stage," because Palestinian needs did not carry the
same imperative: it was merely something they "believed in" (p. 654).
During talks preceding the Clinton Parameters, Ross reports,
Palestinians objected to his advocacy of "Israeli positions that would
deny the Palestinians what they needed to sell a deal: clear
independence, sovereignty over the Haram, and a just solution of the
refugee problem." "I was tough in my response," Ross continues. "They
focused on their needs to the exclusion of the Israeli needs" (p. 724).
It will be noticed that Israeli needs, in Ross's calculus,
systematically trump Palestinian rights.
In his conclusion, Ross observes that the "one unmistakable insight
from the past about the Arabs" is that "No Israeli concession can ever
be too big" (p. 762). However much Israel gives, the Arabs never
"accept that Israel has needs as well—justifying compromise" (p. 763).
What he neglects to mention is that no Israeli "concession" to the
Palestinians required any sacrifice of its rights, whereas the
Palestinians were called upon to sacrifice basic rights for the sake of
Israeli needs. The compromise Israel (and Ross) proffered was not needs
for needs, but Israeli needs at the expense of Palestinian rights.
Indeed, didn't Israel embrace the "needs" framework precisely because
under a "rights" framework it had to withdraw fully from the occupied
Palestinian territory, not to mention allow for the Palestinian right
of return? The same holds true for Israel's relations with the Arab
world in general. "The kind of transformation that would make it
possible for the Arab world to acknowledge that Israel has needs," Ross
laments, "has yet to take place" (p. 763). Translation: Arabs have yet
to understand that Israel's needs trump their rights.
"[T]here can be no deal" between Israel and the Palestinians, according
to Ross, "unless each side is prepared to respond to the essential
needs of the other. . . . [A]greements are forged . . . on the basis of
reconciling needs" (p. 771). One might be forgiven for conceiving that
agreements are generally reached on the basis of law and rights. But
Ross explicitly repudiates this conception. Dissenting from the opinion
of some of his American colleagues, Ross recalls:
Aaron [Miller] was always arguing for a
just and fair proposal. I was not against a fair proposal. But I felt
the very concept of "fairness" was, by definition, subjective.
Similarly both Rob [Malley] and Gamal [Helal] believed that the
Palestinians were entitled to 100 percent of the territory. Swaps
should thus be equal. They believed this was a Palestinian right. Aaron
tended to agree with them not on the basis of right, but on the basis
that every other Arab negotiating partner had gotten 100 percent. Why
should the Palestinians be different? I disagreed. I was focused not on
reconciling rights but on addressing needs. In negotiations, one side's
principle or "right" is usually the other side's impossibility. Of
course, there are irreducible rights. I wanted to address what each
side needed, not what they wanted and not what they felt they were
entitled to. (p. 726)
It is not immediately obvious why a standard of rights reached by broad
international consensus and codified in international law is more
"subjective" than a standard of needs on which there is neither
consensus nor codification. On the issues at hand at Camp David, the
standard of rights was notably uncontroversial in international law.
Although Ross asserts as a flaw of the rights standard that the
respective parties typically disagree on it, this was not the problem
during these negotiations. Clinton did not want to hear about UN
resolutions and international law, but not because they lacked clarity.
Israeli and U.S. negotiators fumed at any mention of rights
because they knew exactly where such talk would lead.
What is most peculiar about Ross's argument is his apparent belief that
his personal adjudication is less arbitrary than reference to a
consensual body of laws. Leaving aside the strange premise that the
transitory opinion of one should count for more than the received
opinion of many, it is unclear what qualifies Ross for the role of
philosopher-king.
[19] On a professional level, his insights on the art of diplomacy will probably not make their way into a textbook,
[20]
while his lengthy affiliation with a think-tank created by the Israel
lobby would seem to cast doubt on his claim to objectivity.
It is his wholesale dismissal of Palestinian needs that ultimately
enables Ross to prove Palestinian culpability for Camp David's failure.
Regarding the Palestinian state's eastern border, Ross delineated on
day one of the Camp David summit that Palestinians had only "symbolic
needs" whereas Israel had "very real and legitimate . . . concerns
about security" (p. 655).
[21]
Regarding Jerusalem, Ross reasoned on day six of Camp David that,
basically, Palestinians needed a token to recoup their losses, such as
having an American embassy in a village abutting the city, so that they
could pretend Jerusalem was their capital: "That would be a big symbol
for Arafat. I said in addition the President could lead an
international delegation that Arafat could host and take to the Haram,
again symbolizing for the world, especially the Arab world, Palestinian
control" (pp. 681–82). Regarding land, Palestinians did not need full
compensation for the territory Israel coveted. Inasmuch as Gaza is one
of the most densely populated areas on earth, and inasmuch as one
aspect of the solution to the refugee problem was that Palestinians
would return to the Palestinian state (but not Israel), one might have
supposed that Palestinians might need, at a bare minimum, full
territorial compensation. But Ross decided otherwise when formulating
the Clinton Parameters: "I felt strongly about 6 to 7 percent
annexation [by Israel] and I was not prepared to lower the ceiling. Nor
was I prepared to introduce the idea of an equivalent swap" (p. 726).
[22] When even
Israeli
negotiators proposed a smaller percentage of Israeli annexation, Ross
reports being "furious"—which gives some sense of his nonpartisan
tallying of Palestinian needs (pp. 748–9).
[23]
On the specific matter of land swaps, Ross had proposed on the eve of
the Camp David summit that Israel "symbolically" exchange territory "as
a way to provide the Palestinians with an explanation for the
modification of borders" (p. 639). Regarding the refugees, too, Ross
consistently maintained that Palestinians had only "symbolic needs" as
against "Israel's practical needs" (pp. 655, 726).
[24]
Judging from Ross's account, Camp David failed because Palestinians
stubbornly clung to the illusion that they had real needs. Had they
understood that all they really needed was symbols, Palestinians would
have leapt at the generous Israeli offer.
[25]
The root of the problem, again, appears to be that Palestinian "sense
of entitlement": Camp David might have succeeded if only Palestinians
grasped that they aren't real, actual human beings.
Norman G. Finkelstein, professor of political science at DePaul
University in Chicago, is the author of numerous books, most recently Beyond Chutzpah: On the Misuse of Anti-Semitism and the Abuse of History
(University of California Press, 2005). He would like to thank Maren
Hackmann, Jeremy Pressman, and Feroze Sidhwa for their comments on an
earlier draft of the extended essay from which this article is drawn.
The full text is being published by IPS as a monograph titled Subordinating Palestinian Rights to Israeli "Needs."
Notes
[1] New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2004. All parenthetical page references in the body of the text refer to Ross's book.
[2] Three distinct phases marked the
Israeli-Palestinian peace negotiations of 2000–1: the Camp David summit
in July 2000, the parameters President Clinton proposed in December
2000, and the Taba negotiations in January 2001. Ross's narrative
covers the first two phases, with Taba getting barely a mention. For
convenience's sake, "Camp David" will denote both the summit and
Clinton proposals. However, where the distinction needs to be made,
"Camp David summit" will denote the first phase and "Clinton
Parameters" the second.
[3] For comprehensive accounts of Camp David based on eyewitnesses, see Charles Enderlin,
Shattered Dreams: The Failure of the Peace Process in the Middle East, 1995–2002 (New York: Other Press, 2002); Clayton E. Swisher,
The Truth about Camp David: The Untold Story about the Collapse of the Middle East Peace Process (New York: Nation Books, 2004); and Jeremy Pressman, "Visions in Collision: What Happened at Camp David and Taba?"
International Security 28, no. 2 (Fall 2003), pp. 5–43.
[4] According to Ross, UN resolution 242 did "not
necessarily mean withdrawal from all the territories captured in 1967"
(p. 815). To support this claim he cites the authority of UN Ambassador
Arthur Goldberg and the Washington Institute for Near East Policy
(WINEP) monograph
UN Security Council Resolution 242: The Building Block of Peacemaking
(Washington: WINEP, 1993). In fact the consensus of the Security
Council (and General Assembly) was that 242 called for full Israeli
withdrawal from the territories it occupied in June 1967 apart from
minor and mutual border adjustments. Goldberg himself is on record as
subscribing to this interpretation during his negotiations with
neighboring Arab states. In any event it is a moot point since the
International Court of Justice authoritatively ruled in 2004 that
Israel must withdraw from all territory conquered in the June 1967 war,
including East Jerusalem, in accordance with the UN Charter principle
barring acquisition of territory by force. (For details see Norman G.
Finkelstein,
Beyond Chutzpah: On the Misuse of Anti-Semitism and the Abuse of History
[Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005], pp. 287–301.) As for
the monographic evidence relied upon by Ross, its quality can be
gleaned from statements such as "the Arab population of the West Bank
and the Gaza Strip" is "often wrongly called 'The Palestinians'" (p.
6), and 242 "does not require the Israelis to transfer to the Arabs
all, most, or indeed any of the occupied territories" (pp. 18–19).
[5] Eyal Benvenisti,
The International Law of Occupation (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), pp. 145–46.
[6] Benvenisti,
International Law, pp. 215–16; cf. p. 187.
[7] Norman G. Finkelstein,
The Rise and Fall of Palestine: A Personal Account of the Intifada Years (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996), pp. 53–56.
[8] Yoram Dinstein,
War, Aggression, and Self-Defense, 4th ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), p. 302. David Cortright and George A. Lopez,
The Sanctions Decade: Assessing UN Strategies in the 1990s
(Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2000). Marc Weller and Barbara Metzger,
"Double Standards" (Negotiations Affairs Department, Palestine
Liberation Organization, 24 September 2002).
[9] Swisher,
The Truth about Camp David, pp. 184, 186 ("couldn't stand," quoting State Department colleague of Ross), 226–27, 228. Enderlin,
Shattered Dreams, pp. 58, 232 ("in league," quoting Arafat). See also Ron Pundak, "From Oslo to Taba: What Went Wrong,"
Survival 43, no. 3 (Autumn 2001), pp. 40–41, which reports that "the American government seemed sometimes to be working
for
the Israeli Prime Minister, as it tried to convince (and pressure) the
Palestinian side to accept Israeli offers" (emphasis in original), and
"Lessons of Arab-Israel Negotiating: Four Negotiators Look Back and
Ahead" (National Press Club, 25 April 2005), where Aaron Miller
observes that "far too often, we functioned in this process, for want
of a better word, as Israel's lawyer" (transcript available at
www.mideasti.org). Pundak is Director-General of the Peres Center for
Peace in Tel Aviv and participated in Israeli-Palestinian negotiations
during the Oslo years, while Miller was on the American delegation at
Camp David.
[10] Enderlin,
Shattered Dreams, p. 202; Swisher,
The Truth about Camp David, p. 275 (citing Enderlin).
[11]
Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory, Advisory Opinion (International Court of Justice, 9 July 2004), 43 IL M 1009 (2004), para. 78.
[12]
Legal Consequences, paras. 119–120; cf.
para. 99. For the World Court opinion, see also Norman G. Finkelstein,
"Reconciling Irreconcilables" (forthcoming).
[13] Amnesty International, "The Right to Return: The
Case of the Palestinians, Policy Statement" (30 March 2001). Human
Rights Watch issued nearly identical statements; see "Human Rights
Watch Urges Attention to Future of Palestinian Refugees" (22 December
2000), and "Israel, Palestinian Leaders Should Guarantee Right of
Return as Part of Comprehensive Refugee Solution" (22 December 2002).
[14] Ross occasionally suggests that it was
Palestinian negotiators rather than Arafat himself who offered these
compromises—e.g., "We had continually moved toward [Arafat]; while his
negotiators moved, he had not moved at all" (p. 708). However, Ross
neither adduces evidence to sustain this claim, nor is it plausible
that the positions presented by Arafat's negotiators fundamentally
differed from his own. Moreover, Ross seems unaware that, were he
correct, his book would make little sense: What point would there be to
reporting in minute detail the positions of Palestinian negotiators if
they represented no one except themselves?
[15] Echoing the Israeli negotiators, Ross writes
that "the Palestinians had come more to maneuver in the souk than to
negotiate a deal" (p. 675). On a side note, although the metaphor is
right, the Israeli negotiators apparently got its subject wrong.
According to Pundak, it was not the Palestinians but Barak who "dragged
his feet and treated the talks like a Persian market. Abu Mazen—the
Palestinian architect of the Oslo accord . . . —repeatedly recommended
that the general principles guiding the Permanent Status Agreement be
established at the outset. . . . But Barak, fearing he would 'expose'
his position too early in the game, rejected this proposal" ("From Oslo
to Taba," p. 39).
[16] Cited in Ron Pundak, "Camp David II: Israel's
Misconceived Approach," p. 7, online at
www.peres-center.org/media/upload/229.pdf.
[17] Compare these passages from Ross:
In the first meeting on territory and
borders, Abu Ala tried a new tack. Whereas previously he would not
discuss security until the Israelis accepted the Palestinian concept of
their eastern border, now he added the condition that he would not
discuss possible modifications to meet Israeli needs on the western
border unless he knew that the total size of the Palestinian territory
would remain unchanged. As he put it, so long as the Palestinian state
would comprise the 6,500 square kilometers that currently made up the
West Bank, Gaza, and East Jerusalem, he could consider modifications to
meet Israeli needs; if not, he could not. This was Abu Ala's way of
trying to get the Israelis to concede both the eastern border and equal
swaps of territory as conditions for considering Israeli needs. This
was, of course, a prescription for going nowhere. (pp. 663–64)
and
Shlomo [Ben-Ami] . . . persuasively
argued it was time for both sides to give up their myths. Israel was
giving up its myths: being in the Jordan Valley forever and not
dividing Jerusalem. These myths were as central to Israel's belief
system as the right of return was to the Palestinians. It was time for
both sides to accept reality and surrender their myths. (p. 721; cf. p.
4)
In the first instance Ross deems the Palestinian tack a nonstarter
because it demands from Israel the impossible "concessions" of
recognizing the legitimate Palestinian border and compensating
Palestinians for the Palestinian territory Israel covets, while in the
second instance he puts on the same plane of unreality Israel's claim
on the Jordan Valley and all of Jerusalem, and the Palestinian right of
return, even if the former claim has no legal basis whereas the latter
one does (leaving aside that Palestinians did in effect surrender it).
[18] See Norman G. Finkelstein,
Image and Reality of the Israel-Palestine Conflict, 2nd ed. (New York: W. W. Norton, 2003), pp. 157–71 (Dayan quote at p. 159).
[19] Nor does Ross's administrative judgment exactly
overwhelm. He reports, for example, that his colleague Toni Verstandig
"had an intuitive feel for economic development" (p. 106). This feel
was on full display at the Camp David summit. Interposing herself
during the intense deliberations between Israeli and Palestinian
negotiators over water, Verstandig said:
"I'm not going to allow these piddly
issues to be a stumbling block to a peace agreement!" With that,
witnesses recalled, she took the eraser, wiped off the formulations,
and with a piece of chalk drew an elongated dollar sign. After slamming
the chalk down and facing the group, her words would leave them
speechless: "Just tell me how much!" (Swisher, The Truth about Camp David, pp. 296–97)
[20] For example, "it is good to learn your
interlocutor's position before revealing your own" (p. 54), "when you
have momentum, don't stop; build on it, and work around the clock" (p.
277), "when you can close an issue, do so" (p. 403), "surprise always
stretches the time needed to overcome problems" (p. 437).
[21] In fact the Jordan Valley apparently had no
military value for Israel. Shlomo Ben-Ami refers to it as a
"mythological strategic asset" (Shlomo Ben-Ami,
Scars of War, Wounds of Peace: The Israeli-Arab Tragedy
[New York: Oxford University Press, 2006], p. 270), while Ross himself
reports that "Even the IDF acknowledged that the eastern border in the
Jordan Valley and along the river was less significant than
historically thought" (p. 636) and that it was one of "Israel's myths"
that it "could never surrender the Jordan Valley lest it give up its
essential security border" (p. 774; but cf. p. 616).
[22] Some 1.4 million Gazans live on 365 square
kilometers of land, or 4,000 Gazans per square kilometer, as compared
to the Israeli population density of 300 per square kilometer. Ross was
hardly unaware of these grim realities when he decided Palestinians
could do with less territory, for he himself quotes Palestinians on
this point:
Saeb [Erekat] spoke of enlarging the
size of the swap area adjacent to Gaza to relieve the terrible
population density there. [Muhammad] Dahlan was especially poignant on
this subject, observing that we were asking for 8 percent annexation of
the West Bank to accommodate 80 percent of Israel's 200,000 Israeli
settlers. He pointed out that they were asking us to increase the size
of the swap area to relieve the pressure on 1.2 million Palestinians
living in Gaza—an area roughly equal in size to the area we now said
the Israelis would need to annex for the "comfort" of their settlers in
the West Bank. (p. 724)
[23] In his epilogue, Ross seems to sanction Israel's
annexation of a much higher percentage of the West Bank in the event of
a unilateral Israeli withdrawal. Putting aside the veracity of the
various percentage-offers he cites, the basis of his revised
calculation perplexes. Reporting that Israel will need to annex 15–20
percent of the West Bank to absorb about 75 percent of the settlers, he
writes: "At Camp David and again in the Clinton ideas we spoke of three
settlement blocs that could accommodate 80 percent of the settlers. But
we were focused on an agreement that would annex these areas to Israel
and for which there would be some territorial compensation to the
Palestinians" (p. 798). The Clinton Parameters called for Israeli
annexation of about 5 percent of the West Bank. If Israel could absorb
80 percent of the settlers on the basis of a 5 percent annexation, why
does it need to annex 15–20 percent of the West Bank to absorb 75
percent of the settlers?
[24] It appears that Barak shared Ross's conception
of Palestinian needs. For example, just prior to the Camp David summit
he estimated that in the event of a peace settlement Israel "would need
$23 billion to meet security and resettlement needs" and an additional
"$10 billion in loan guarantees," whereas "he saw the Palestinians
needing $5 billion" (p. 500). Israel's per capita national income
hovered around $17,000, Palestine's around $1,000.
[25] Ross's contempt for Palestinians is of a piece
with his treatment of Arafat. He warns Arafat that "there better not be
any surprises tomorrow. No holdups, no questions, no reluctance to
sign. Any of that takes place and you lose President Clinton.
Understood?" (p. 207). He impresses on Arafat that "it is remarkable
that the President took time out from campaigning to call you" (p.
286), and browbeats Arafat to "not let Clinton down" (pp. 301, 416).
Before an encounter with Netanyahu, he threatens Arafat "Don't just
come to the meeting, make sure you give me a gift from that meeting
that I can take to President Clinton" (p. 302). Later, he wows Arafat,
saying that "President Clinton was prepared to assume the 'risk and
responsibility' of launching an American initiative to save the peace
process. These words, I said, should convey great meaning to you" (p.
341), and chides Arafat that "he had disappointed President Clinton . .
. there were costs for him in disappointing Clinton" (p. 372). It seems
a fair inference that Ross didn't speak in this tone to Asad, and the
reason is not hard to find. "Barak was also far more attracted to
dealing with Hafez al-Asad than to dealing with Yasir Arafat," Ross
reports. "In his eyes, Asad was everything Arafat wasn't. He commanded
a real state, with a real army, with thousands of tanks and hundreds of
missiles" (p. 509; cf. p. 90). Like Barak, Ross evidently respected the
Syrian strongman, whereas Arafat was seen as just a two-bit terrorist.